Results for 'Henry S. Macran'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Hegel's Science of Logic.W. H. Johnston, L. G. Struthers & Henry S. Macran - 1929 - Humana Mente 4 (16):561-562.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  7
    Hegel's Doctrine of Formal Logic: Being a Translation of the First, Section of the Subjective Logic (Classic Reprint).Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel & Henry S. Macran (eds.) - 2008 - Oxford, England: Forgotten Books.
    Excerpt from Hegel's Doctrine of Formal Logic: Being a Translation of the First, Section of the Subjective Logic It has been my great good fortune to have freely at my disposal during the preparation of this work the wide knowledge and wise judgement of my friend Dr. James Creed Meredith. I am indeed deeply in his debt for his valuable assistance, ever ready to my call but I can console myself by reflecting that the reader is still more indebted to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  58
    Hegel's Science of Logic. Translated by W. H. Johnston B.A., and L. G. Struthers M.A. With an Introductory Preface by Viscount Haldane of Cloan, K.T., P.C., O.M., F.R.S. (London: George Allen and Unwin Ltd. 1929. Vol. I, pp. 404; Vol. II, pp. 486. Price 32s. 2 vols.)Hegel's Logic of World and Idea. Being a translation of the second and third parts of the Subjective Logic; with an Introduction on Idealism, Limited and Absolute. By Henry S. Macran, Fellow of Trinity College and Professor of Moral Philosophy in the University of Dublin. (Oxford: at the Clarendon Press, 1929. Pp. 215. Price 12s. 6d.). [REVIEW]J. S. Mackenzie - 1929 - Philosophy 4 (16):561-.
  4. Truth and Ends in Dewey's Pragmatism.Henry S. Richardson - 1998 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 24:109-147.
    Dewey's voluminous writings, spanning decades and reflecting the contrasting national moods of different historical periods, abound with tensions, not to say contradictions. In highlighting and working with a conflict within Dewey's commitments, then, I do not mean to be catching him out or correcting a mistake. The tension on which I focus is one with which he struggled for most of his philosophical career and one that he never satisfactorily resolved, yet it is also one that goes to the heart (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Institutionally Divided Moral Responsibility*: HENRY S. RICHARDSON.Henry S. Richardson - 1999 - Social Philosophy and Policy 16 (2):218-249.
    I am going to be discussing a mode of moral responsibility that anglophone philosophers have largely neglected. It is a type of responsibility that looks to the future rather than the past. Because this forward-looking moral responsibility is relatively unfamiliar in the lexicon of analytic philosophy, many of my locutions will initially strike many readers as odd. As a matter of everyday speech, however, the notion of forward-looking moral responsibility is perfectly familiar. Today, for instance, I said I would be (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  6.  33
    Discerning Subordination and Inviolability: A Comment on Kamm's Intricate Ethics: Henry S. Richardson.Henry S. Richardson - 2008 - Utilitas 20 (1):81-91.
    Frances Kamm has for some time now been a foremost champion of non-consequentialist ethics. One of her most powerful non-consequentialist themes has been the idea of inviolability. Morality's prohibitions, she argues, confer on persons the status of inviolability. This thought helps articulate a rationale for moral prohibitions that will resist the protean threat posed by the consequentialist argument that anyone should surely be willing to violate a constraint if doing so will minimize the overall number of such violations. As Kamm (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  7. The calculus of individuals and its uses.Henry S. Leonard & Nelson Goodman - 1940 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 5 (2):45-55.
  8. The Orthodox Foundation of Religion Long Since Collected by That Iudicious and Elegant Man, Mr. Henry Ainsworth, for the Benefit of His Private Company, and Now Divulged for the Publike Good of All That Desire to Know That Cornerstone, Christ Jesus Crucified.Henry Ainsworth & W. S. - 1641 - Printed by R.C. For M. Sparke, Junior.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  17
    Articulating the Moral Community: Toward a Constructive Ethical Pragmatism.Henry S. Richardson - 2018 - New York, US: Oup Usa.
    Henry S. Richardson is Professor of Philosophy at Georgetown University. From 2008-18, he was the editor of Ethics. His previous books include Practical Reasoning about Final Ends, Democratic Autonomy, and Moral Entanglements. He has held fellowships sponsored by the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation, the National Endowment for the Humanities, and the University Center for Human Values at Princeton University.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  10.  38
    The Calculus of Individuals and Its Uses.Henry S. Leonard & Nelson Goodman - 1940 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 5 (3):113-114.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   136 citations  
  11.  85
    Practical Reasoning About Final Ends.Henry S. Richardson - 1994 - Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
    Henry Richardson argues that we can determine our ends rationally. He constructs a rich and original theory of how we can reason about our final goals. Richardson defuses the counter-arguments for the limits of rational deliberation, and develops interesting ideas about how his model might be extended to interpersonal deliberation of ends, taking him to the borders of political theory. Along the way Richardson offers illuminating discussions of, inter alia, Aristotle, Aquinas, Sidgwick, and Dewey, as well as the work (...)
  12.  15
    Précis of Democratic Autonomy.Henry S. Richardson - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 71 (1):187–195.
  13. Specifying norms as a way to resolve concrete ethical problems.Henry S. Richardson - 1990 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 19 (4):279-310.
  14.  9
    Moral Entanglements: The Ancillary-Care Obligations of Medical Researchers.Henry S. Richardson - 2012 - Oup Usa.
    The philosopher Henry Richardson's short book is a defense of a position on a neglected topic in medical research ethics. Clinical research ethics has been a longstanding area of study, dating back to the aftermath of the Nazi death-camp doctors and the Tuskegee syphilis study. Most ethical regulations and institutions have developed in response to those past abuses, including the stress on obtaining informed consent from the subject. Richardson points out that that these ethical regulations do not address one (...)
    No categories
  15.  25
    Practical Reasoning About Final Ends.Henry S. Richardson - 1994 - Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
    Henry Richardson argues that we can determine our ends rationally. He constructs a rich and original theory of how we can reason about our final goals. Richardson defuses the counter-arguments for the limits of rational deliberation, and develops interesting ideas about how his model might be extended to interpersonal deliberation of ends, taking him to the borders of political theory. Along the way Richardson offers illuminating discussions of, inter alia, Aristotle, Aquinas, Sidgwick, and Dewey, as well as the work (...)
  16.  52
    The Ancillary‐Care Responsibilities of Medical Researchers: An Ethical Framework for Thinking about the Clinical Care that Researchers Owe Their Subjects.Henry S. Richardson & Leah Belsky - 2004 - Hastings Center Report 34 (1):25-33.
    Researchers do not owe their subjects the same level of care that physicians owe patients, but they owe more than merely what the research protocol stipulates. In keeping with the dynamics of the relationship between researcher and subject, they have limited but substantive fiduciary obligations.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   85 citations  
  17. Specifying, balancing, and interpreting bioethical principles.Henry S. Richardson - 2000 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25 (3):285 – 307.
    The notion that it is useful to specify norms progressively in order to resolve doubts about what to do, which I developed initially in a 1990 article, has been only partly assimilated by the bioethics literature. The thought is not just that it is helpful to work with relatively specific norms. It is more than that: specification can replace deductive subsumption and balancing. Here I argue against two versions of reliance on balancing that are prominent in recent bioethical discussions. Without (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  18.  43
    Incidental Findings and Ancillary-Care Obligations.Henry S. Richardson - 2008 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 36 (2):256-270.
    Recent work on incidental fndings, concentrating on the difcult problems posed by the ambiguous results often generated by high-tech medicine, has proceeded largely independently from recent work on medical researchers' ancillary-care obligations, the obligations that researchers have to deal with diseases or conditions besides the one(s) under study. This paper contends that the two topics are morally linked, and specifcally that a sound understanding of ancillary-care obligations will center them on incidental fndings. The paper sets out and defends an understanding (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  19. Practical Reasoning about Final Ends.Henry S. Richardson - 1996 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 58 (4):782-783.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  20. Moral Reasoning.Henry S. Richardson - 2013 - The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Moral reasoning is individual or collective practical reasoning about what, morally, one ought to do. Philosophical examination of moral reasoning faces both distinctive puzzles — about how we recognize moral considerations and cope with conflicts among them and about how they move us to act — and distinctive opportunities for gleaning insight about what we ought to do from how we reason about what we ought to do.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  21.  29
    Incidental Findings and Ancillary-Care Obligations.Henry S. Richardson - 2008 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 36 (2):256-270.
    This paper explores the convergence of two recent and growing streams of bioethical work and concern. Each has originated independently, but each arises from the fact that the Common Rule that has shaped medical research ethics, as institutionalized in the United States and also abroad, is largely silent about what needs to be done in response to researchers’ positive obligations. One stream concerns what to do about the sometimes vast range of findings that may arise incidentally to performing research procedures. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  22. Rawlsian social-contract theory and the severely disabled.Henry S. Richardson - 2006 - The Journal of Ethics 10 (4):419-462.
    Martha Nussbaum has powerfully argued in Frontiers ofJustice and elsewhere that John Rawls’s sort of social-contract theory cannot usefully be deployed to deal with issues pertaining to justice for the disabled. To counter this claim, this article deploys Rawls’s sort of social-contract theory in order to deal with issues pertaining to justice for the disabled—or, since, as Nussbaum stresses, we all have some degree of disability—for the severely disabled. In this way, rather than questioning one by one Nussbaum’s interpretive claims (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  23.  27
    Measurement, pleasure, and practical science in Plato's Protagoras.Henry S. Richardson - 1990 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 28 (1):7-32.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Measurement, Pleasure, and Practical Science in Plato's Protagoras HENRY S. RICHARDSON 1. INTRODUCTION TOWARDS THE END OF THE PROTAGORAS Socrates suggests that the "salvation of our life" depends upon applying to pleasures and pains a science of measurement (metr$tik~techn~).Whether Plato intended to portray Socrates as putting forward sincerely the form of hedonism that makes these pleasures and pains relevant has been the subject of a detailed and probably (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  5
    Measurement, Pleasure, and Practical Science in Plato's Protagoras.Henry S. Richardson - 1990 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 28 (1):7-32.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Measurement, Pleasure, and Practical Science in Plato's Protagoras HENRY S. RICHARDSON 1. INTRODUCTION TOWARDS THE END OF THE PROTAGORAS Socrates suggests that the "salvation of our life" depends upon applying to pleasures and pains a science of measurement (metr$tik~techn~).Whether Plato intended to portray Socrates as putting forward sincerely the form of hedonism that makes these pleasures and pains relevant has been the subject of a detailed and probably (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  82
    Degrees of finality and the highest good in Aristotle.Henry S. Richardson - 1992 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 30 (3):327-352.
    This article develops a uniform interpretation of "pursuit for the sake of an end", explaining what an "unqualified final" end (sought solely for its own sake) offers that a (merely) final one does not and providing an improved account of what Aristotle means by an "ultimate end". This interpretation sheds light on (1) the regress argument at the outset of "N.E." I.2, (2) the way Aristotle argues for the existence of a highest good, (3) the special contribution of "self-sufficiency" (autarkeia) (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  26. The logic of existence.Henry S. Leonard - 1956 - Philosophical Studies 7 (4):49 - 64.
  27.  42
    Autonomy's Many Normative Presuppositions.Henry S. Richardson - 2001 - American Philosophical Quarterly 38 (3):287 - 303.
  28. Liberalism, Deliberative Democracy, and “Reasons that All Can Accept”.Henry S. Richardson & James Bohman - 2009 - Journal of Political Philosophy 17 (3):253-274.
  29.  43
    Truth and Ends in Dewey's Pragmatism.Henry S. Richardson - 1998 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 28 (sup1):109-147.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  30.  96
    Beyond Good and Right: Toward a Constructive Ethical Pragmatism.Henry S. Richardson - 1995 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 24 (2):108-141.
  31.  11
    The mother's confessional.Henry S. Curtis - 1921 - International Journal of Ethics 31 (2):200-202.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  14
    The Mother's Confessional.Henry S. Curtis - 1920 - International Journal of Ethics 31 (2):200.
  33.  7
    The Mother's Confessional.Henry S. Curtis - 1921 - International Journal of Ethics 31 (2):200-202.
  34.  18
    Commensurability as a Prerequisite of Rational Choice: An Examination of Sidgwick's Position.Henry S. Richardson - 1991 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 8 (2):181 - 197.
  35.  21
    Bioethics: A Return to Fundamentals.Henry S. Richardson, Bernard Gert, Charles M. Culver & K. Danner Clouser - 1999 - Hastings Center Report 29 (5):36.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  36.  34
    Announcing an Improvement to the Journal’s Blind Review Process.Henry S. Richardson - 2017 - Ethics 127 (3):519-520.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37. Satisficing: Not good enough.Henry S. Richardson - 2004 - In Michael Byron (ed.), Satisficing and Maximizing: Moral Theorists on Practical Reason. Cambridge University Press. pp. 106--130.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  38.  57
    Estlund’s Promising Account of Democratic Authority.Henry S. Richardson - 2011 - Ethics 121 (2):301-334.
    David Estlund’s Democratic Authority develops a novel doctrine of “normative consent,” according to which the nonconsent of those with a duty to consent is null. This article suggests that this doctrine can be defended by confining it to contexts involving consent to an authority, which raise distinctive normative challenges, but argues that Estlund’s attempt to deploy the doctrine fails, for it does not provide convincing reasons to think that citizens have any duty to consent. In closing, the article suggests that (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  39.  80
    Relying on Experts as We Reason Together.Henry S. Richardson - 2012 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 22 (2):91-110.
    In various contexts, it is thought to be important that we reason together. For instance, an attractive conception of democracy requires that citizens reach lawmaking decisions by reasoning with one another. Reasoning requires that reasoners survey the considerations that they take to be reasons, proceed by a coherent train of thought, and reach conclusions freely. De facto reliance on experts threatens the possibility of collective reasoning by making some reasons collectively unsurveyable, raising questions about the coherence of the resulting train (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  40.  53
    The Logical Structure of Sittlichkeit.Henry S. Richardson - 1989 - Idealistic Studies 19 (1):62-78.
    Sittlichkeit seduces: Hegel’s third category of Right, intended to synthesize impartially derived rights with a subjectively centered morality of the good, understandably piques the hopes of his modern readers. How could it not? Sittlichkeit, Ethical Life, holds out the prospect of so much that we still seek. It promises to reconcile welfare and autonomy while guaranteeing concrete content for their product. By combining legal duty with a place for conscience and freedom, it could solve a central problem of politics. Most (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  41.  98
    Interrogatives, imperatives, truth, falsity and lies.Henry S. Leonard - 1959 - Philosophy of Science 26 (3):172-186.
    This paper aims to establish three major theses: (1) Not only declarative sentences, but also interrogatives and imperatives, may be classified as true or as false. (2) Declarative, imperative, and interrogative utterances may also be classified as honest or as dishonest. (3) Whether an utterance is honest or dishonest is logically independent of whether it is true or is false. The establishment of the above theses follows upon the adoption of a principle for identifying what is meant by any sentence, (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  42.  80
    Long as you love me, it's alright?Henry S. Richardson - 2003 - Philosophical Studies 116 (2):183-195.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43. Les droits de l'animal considérés dans leur rapport avec le progrés social.Henry S. Salt & L. Hotelin - 1900 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 50:96-99.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Tennyson as a Thinker.Henry S. Salt - 1910 - International Journal of Ethics 20 (4):513-514.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Discerning subordination and inviolability: A comment on Kamm's intricate ethics.Henry S. Richardson - 2008 - Utilitas 20 (1):81-91.
    Frances Kamm has for some time now been a foremost champion of non-consequentialist ethics. One of her most powerful non-consequentialist themes has been the idea of inviolability. Morality's prohibitions, she argues, confer on persons the status of inviolability. This thought helps articulate a rationale for moral prohibitions that will resist the protean threat posed by the consequentialist argument that anyone should surely be willing to violate a constraint if doing so will minimize the overall number of such violations. As Kamm (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  46.  5
    Précis of Democratic Autonomy.Henry S. Richardson - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 71 (1):187-187.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47.  23
    Development and main outlines in Rawls's Theory of justice.Henry S. Richardson (ed.) - 1999 - New York: Garland.
    His 1971 masterpiece, A Theory of Justice, permanently changed the landscape of moral political theory, revitalizing the normative study of social issues and ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. 10. Neil MacCormick, Practical Reason in Law and Morality Neil MacCormick, Practical Reason in Law and Morality (pp. 192-196).Henry S. Richardson, Cécile Fabre, Joshua Glasgow, Alison Hills, Kieran Setiya & Hallie Rose Liberto - 2009 - In John Hawthorne (ed.), Ethics. Wiley Periodicals.
  49. The problem of liberalism and the good.Henry S. Richardson - 1990 - In R. Bruce Douglass, Gerald M. Mara & Henry S. Richardson (eds.), Liberalism and the good. New York: Routledge. pp. 1--28.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  50.  27
    "Another ethics consultant looks at Mr. B's case: commentary on" An ethical dilemma.Henry S. Perkins - 1990 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 1 (2):126-132.
1 — 50 / 1000